Wednesday, December 14, 2011

Rule of law: neither thin nor thick

This is the second article on the criticism that Joseph Raz directed against F. A. Hayek. Link to the 1st article

A false dilemma
     One of the most common ways in which thinkers mislead other people (often without meaning to) consists in presenting false choices between alternatives. When both alternatives are wrong, confusion is guaranteed.
     In discussing the notion of the rule of law, law professors have managed to create one of those misleading dilemmas. They tell us that we have to choose between a thin and a fat (or thick) concept of the rule of law. I think that both gravely distort the concept.
     Professor Joseph Raz, a law scholar at Oxford, is the champion of the thin notion. Most of his colleagues defend the fat version –among these, the late Tom Bingham, Lord Chief Justice of Britain. One kills the rule of law by starvation, the other by overfeeding.
     To sum up the choices that I will analyze, one can say that Raz’s thin notion reduces the rule of law to some formal properties, most of them related to trials and the work of judges, but without much content. So for instance, Raz states that the rule of law means that laws and statutes are clear -not vague-, that judges are independent, that judges have review powers over parliamentary legislation, that courts should be easily accessible, and some other principles. But apart from that, the laws themselves may have any content. Raz includes “the principles of natural justice” such as fair hearing and absence of bias as essential for the correct application of the law (of whatever content). As said, his principles refer mostly to procedure and the work of judges.

     The thick notion requires much more. Its advocates enumerate rights that laws must recognize so that a legal system can be said to uphold the rule of law. The list of rights may be shorter or longer according to the writer.

     In Raz’s opinion, those who support the fat notion of the rule of law make the same mistake people make with the notion of democracy: they often ascribe to it all the good characteristics they want to see in a legal system. By doing that, the notion becomes useless. Raz argues that we should not confuse the rule of law with the rule of good law. As we saw in the first article about his criticism of Hayek, Raz says that the rule of law must not be confused with democracy, justice, equality before the law, human rights of any kind, or respect for persons or for the dignity of man (The Rule of law and its virtue, page 211, included in The Authority of Law, Oxford University Press, 1979, reprinted 2002).
     Rather than a thin notion, I think that Raz’s is an empty notion of the rule of law. We've seen in the first article that Raz does not controvert Hayek’s account of the rule of law. He disputes the value that Hayek sees in it. In rejecting the fat (or thick) notion, he asserts that he is “following in the footsteps of Hayek and many others who understood ‘the rule of law’ in similar ways” (p. 211). I do not think that is correct; I think Raz failed to understand Hayek. Link to my article: Misreading Hayek.

Rule of law: not a blueprint for a constitution
     Hayek wrote that what people understand by “law” when they refer to the government of the laws is not any law that the legislature approves. He wrote in The Road to Serfdom that “The idea that there is no limit to the powers of the legislator is in part a result of popular sovereignty and democratic government. It has been strengthened by the belief that, so long as all actions of the state are duly authorized by legislation, the Rule of Law will be preserved. But this is completely to misconceive the meaning of the Rule of Law. This rule has little to do with the question whether all actions of government are legal in the juridical sense. They may well be and yet not conform to the Rule of Law…It may well be that Hitler has obtained his unlimited powers in a strictly constitutional manner and that whatever he does is therefore legal in the juridical sense. But who would suggest for that reason that the Rule of Law still prevails in Germany?” (p. 91, 50th edition).
     That was written in 1944. In the preface he wrote in 1976 Hayek says that when he asked whether anyone would say that nonsense about Hitler’s government, he considered it a rhetorical question, only to find that professors Hans Kelsen (a very influential law scholar before and after the war) and Harold Laski (a British Labour politician) had maintained precisely that.
     So, not just any law is compatible with the rule of law. Not the edicts against the press of some Politburo or the confiscations allowed by the many Latin American permanent emergency laws and sanctioned by their courts. But then, what rules and rights? Too few or too many? Should we choose a thin or a fat rule of law?
    The choice is misleading, and in itself reproduces a fundamental mistake against which Hayek warned us. The task does not consist in making a list, short or long, of the rights we would like to have. Those who discuss whether “the rule of law” should include a shorter or longer list of rights have in mind a constitution. Our way of thinking in terms of constitutions and declarations of rights leads us to apply the same scheme to “the rule of law” but that is alien to the idea.

What rights are covered? All of them
     We received that idea from a long tradition of Western thought and practice. To a large extent, it is an English concept. A.V. Dicey was one of the most renowned English law scholars at a time when the notion of rule of law was still understood by English scholars. Therefore Hayek often refers to Dicey’s The Law of the Constitution (link to the full text ).
     When I say that the notion of the rule of law is no longer understood by many contemporary English law scholars I don’t mean to be disrespectful. I only mean that in their efforts to get a list of rights, judicial review, and possibly a written constitution, they have moved such a distance from English traditions that their way of reasoning is closer to that of German or American law scholars than to Dicey’s. Take for instance one of the most insightful and intriguing remarks made by him: he wrote that the British constitution is not the source but the consequence of the rights of individuals (The Law of the Constitution p. 121). That applies not only to John Smith’s right to his farm, but also to his right to vote at elections. Dicey says that in England the principles of private law have been so extended by the Courts and Parliament as to determine the position of the Crown and of its servants “thus the constitution is the result of the ordinary law of the land”.
     Law professors usually criticize English law because it lacks a list of constitutional rights. What they do not realize is that in the classic English understanding, all rights were equal, all had equal protection, all were constitutional. Or better, the distinction between constitutional and non-constitutional rights made no sense. If you had a right, a true right and not a wish or a privilege granted by some bureau, then it was part of the law of the land as much as the succession to the Crown.
Dicey tells us that “To say that the ‘constitution guaranteed’ one class of rights more than the other would be to an Englishman an unnatural or a senseless form of speech” (p. 119).
     It is also necessary to bear in mind that Dicey says that the principles of private law (contracts, torts, etc.) formed the basis of the constitution. In the continent, in the US, and probably in contemporary UK, the process is the reverse: we descend from public law to private law. In my country, Argentina, law scholars have been pushing public law principles into private law since the 30’s, and that is still considered “the modern trend”. Private law becomes less private each year, as it is mostly concerned with social goals, rights of minorities, and fair prices for consumers.

     So, what was covered by the rule of law in its original understanding? Everything; and the exceptions were viewed as such, as anomalies to be fixed or kept, but always suspected and distrusted. That laws ruled meant that all rights, be them contractual claims or the vote, were subject to general and abstract laws that described situations (buying a car, stealing a car) in which anyone could find himself at one moment or other. The question whether the list of rights should be short or long is nonsensical. Again, this is not meant to be disrespectful of the renowned thinkers who pose and decide that question in one way or the other. It merely shows that they refer to “the rule of law” in the same way in which they talk of a constitution or a human rights convention.
     The rule of law covers every right –the rights that I have, not the rights that I want to have. The house that I bought, not the one that I would have liked to buy. The right to apply for a job, not the right to force employers to hire me. As Edmund Burke said: we have equal rights, but not to the same things. That “the law rules and not men” means that these things belong to me by law, not because some official thought it best to adjudicate them to me. That right, and all the other rights that I have, and all the rights that people have, are the content of the rule of law.
     But then, what if we happen to live in a situation where for most people those rights are few, as were those of peasants in medieval England? What if some men have a right of life and death over some others? Is it not true then that –as Raz writes- the rule of law might in principle cover very little? Well, that is true in a most peculiar way: it is true if we think of a situation that is not true.
     Certainly, if we go back many centuries we find few and uncertain rights, but then we also find that there was little of what we know as the rule of law. Hayek's analysis does not refer to the Middle Ages, that is quite clear.

No historical coincidence
     By the time the ideal of the rule of law had developed, Englishmen enjoyed more rights (and more certain rights) than most other people, and no Englishman had a right of life and death over others. More importantly, that fact wasn’t mere historical coincidence. It wasn’t by chance that where law ruled, people had more rights –and more certain rights- than in other places. The system wasn’t perfect, but it was infinitely better than arbitrary rule. And it was perfecting itself all the time.
     Edmund Burke compared the English way of securing some rights and then advancing with a mortmain. You secure some capital of rights and then try to improve. The comparison is instructive, because it is the capital that you already have secured that allows you to acquire more.
     Of course, we can argue that it is possible to think of the rule of law in isolation, without referring to all the rights that grew with it, as free speech, habeas corpus, property rights, limited taxation, subjection of public officials to the law of the land, and many others. But our powers of abstraction are no ground for denying that in history, rights and the rule of law are born and die together.

Distorting the meaning of the rule of law
     As Hayek pointed out, we can’t have both the rule of law and government planning. When we advance on one direction, we retreat from the other. We can’t have both the rule of law and “positive discrimination”.
     Joseph Raz claims that after all the rule of law is not so important, that it has no moral value in itself. As I said in the first article in which I criticized his criticism, he failed to understand Hayek’s main arguments. But he also removes from the notion a great deal of its content. Even more confusingly, Raz adds content that do not belong to it.
     As to the latter, Raz tells us in his enumeration of what the rule of law requires that “The courts should have review powers over the implementation of the other principles. This includes review of both subordinate and parliamentary legislation and of administrative action, but in itself it is a very limited review –merely to ensure conformity to the rule of law” (6th point in the enumeration, p. 217). It seems that Raz thinks that one of the requisites of the rule of law is that judges have review powers, and that he includes parliamentary legislation in those powers. That is odd because it would mean that England, the land where the notion developed, was at the same time the land were people failed to see one of its requisites. The issue cannot be treated here at length, but clearly judicial review of parliamentary decisions is no requisite of the rule of law. Some may consider that it is a better safeguard against parliamentary arbitrariness, but of course judicial review provides no remedy against judicial arbitrariness –it may even encourage it. The rule of law is not –and has never been- an answer to the question: Who has the last word on constitutional issues? As Hayek writes: "Whether, as in some countries, the main applications of the Rule of Law are laid down in a bill of rights or in a constitutional code, or whether the principle is merely a firmly established tradition, matters comparatively little" (The Road to Serfdom, 93).
     Raz also removes from the notion content that truly belongs to it. He writes that retroactive laws do not conflict with the rule of law if “it is known for certain that a retroactive law will the enacted” (p. 214). The assertion is very questionable. If all that is known is that some law will be enacted but not its content, then all we know is that the lawgiver will act in some way or other –and that is clearly in conflict with the rule of law. If on the other hand we know that a law will be enacted and we know for certain what its content will be, then that law is retroactive only in name or form –but that is an unreal situation and certainty is almost impossible to be real before the law is actually enacted.
     In any case, I don’t think it advisable to try to reconcile the rule of law and retroactive laws –not with such a vague formula as that provided by Raz. After all, the principle against retroactive rules has always been one of the most definite elements in the idea of the rule of law.
     It is alarming to see that the American law scholar Ronald Dworkin agrees with Raz when he writes that it might be enough to warn the population that moral standards will be applied in judging particular behavior (see his book Justice in Robes, 176). Raz’s exception in favor of retroactive legislation is ambiguous; Dworkin’s is vague –which is worse because more difficult to disentangle.
     Raz also writes that the rule of law does not mean equality, and he adds “before the law or otherwise” (p. 211). But it is certain that equality before the law is one of the central elements of the idea of the rule of law as it has been understood for generations, and that cannot be dismissed by simply telling us that it is not. Of course, I do not know what Raz includes in his otherwise but if he means equality of income or fortune, then it is clearly not part of the meaning of the rule of law. As Hayek explained, it is against it.

The rule of law is not a law
     Of course, there are exceptions to a perfect equality before the law. Minors are treated differently, and in the past women too. But even then we must not base general conclusions on exceptions. The rule of law is not a law, it is an ideal; it is a conception about law, about government, and about liberty. Besides, the inequality of minors has definite limits –and the same applies to the situation of women in the past. The right of a minor to his inheritance is protected by the law as much as that of an adult –the limitations apply to the exercise that a minor can make of that right over his possessions. Women were protected in their persons and property no less than men. Certainly, there were some differences as to the way of disposing of their property, the right to vote, etc. But we must keep a sense of proportion: even in Victorian times, English women enjoyed more certain rights than most other women in Europe –not to mention the rest of the world.

Judges are not the main players
     Another way in which Raz’s explanation misleads us about the content of the idea of the rule of law is that he exaggerates the importance of the work of judges. Most of his principles apply to what he describes as the machinery of enforcing the law (p. 218). That is a common error of law scholars (or rather a lack of perspective) against which Hayek warned us.
     Hayek says about the certainty of the law: “It has become the fashion to belittle the extent to which such certainty can be achieved, and there are understandable reasons why lawyers, concerned mainly with litigation, are apt to do so. They have normally to deal with cases in which the outcome is uncertain. But the degree of certainty of the law must be judged by the disputes which do not lead to litigation because the outcome is practically certain as soon as the legal position is examined. It is the cases that never come before the courts, not those that do, that are the measure of the certainty of the law. The modern tendency to exaggerate this uncertainty is part of the campaign against the rule of law…” (The Constitution of Liberty, p. 208).
     Without denying that people may apply rules by themselves, lawyers and law professors tend to focus on the application of rules by judges. When that is coupled with a misleading way of referring to judicial and administrative decisions by the name of “particular laws” (thus creating a false analogy between them and true laws) we are almost bound to misunderstand what is crucial for the rule of law.
     Raz tells us that “what the doctrine requires is the subjection of particular laws to general, open, and stable ones. It is one of the important principles of the doctrine that the making of particular laws should be guided by open and relatively stable general rules” (p. 213). That is not wrong, but it puts the stress on the wrong place.
     There is yet another false analogy lurking when we say that general rules “guide” both judges and ordinary people. The latter pay attention to laws in order to pursue their own plans. To use Hayek’s image, they use road signposts to guide them in following the path they have chosen according to their preferences. Judges aren’t guided by laws in that way when they decide a case –or rather, they should not.

Monday, November 28, 2011

Joseph Raz against Friedrich Hayek on the rule of law

 This is the first of three articles on the criticism that Joseph Raz directed against Hayek’s defense of the rule of law. 
It is strange to see an economist (Hayek) stressing the value of the rule of law, and a law professor (Raz) contradicting him. I think that Raz made three mistakes, and they will be the subjects of the three articles. I will sum up their content:
1st. article:  Raz fails to understand Hayek’s main points.
2d. article: Raz strips from the notion of the rule of law  most of the content that belongs to it according to history and to common understanding; and he adds things that do not belong to it.
3d. article: Raz tries to show that the rule of law might be of no value in authoritarian non-Western nations. That doesn’t prove that the rule of law has little value for free Western nations (which are included in Raz’s low estimation of the rule of law). But in fact, Raz’s argument is also wrong concerning non-Western nations.
I have added another article, where I try to explain what I think is the main misunderstanding about Hayek's concept of the rule of law

An economist revives the interest in the rule of law
     A person not acquainted with the ideological map of the XXth century would find it surprising that it was Friedrich Hayek, an economist, who first revived the interest in the notion of the rule of law. He dedicated chapter V of his book The Road to Serfdom (link to a condensed version) to the analysis of the relations between planning and the rule of law. Hayek’s concern about that issue appears again in his other books.
     The notion of the rule of law had been neglected during most part of the XXth century –not without horrible consequences. Hayek rediscovered it and tried to put it back on the ideological map. That was odd enough and tells a lot about that map.
     But it was more surprising still, and more revealing, that it was a prominent law scholar at Oxford, Joseph Raz, who criticized Hayek’s efforts, and also –with just a few derogatory remarks– the great British thinkers that had taught the notion of the rule of law to generations of lawyers and politicians.


Hayek's ideas
     Hayek showed that there is a conflict between planning and the rule of law. He explained why it was possible to reach an agreement about rules, but not about planning at a national scale. When planning is confined to a single industry there may be agreement among capitalists and workers that it would be a fine thing to impose a ban on foreign products. But when the choices are whether to increase the salaries of nurses or of agricultural workers, have better schools or more generators in power plants, “nothing short of a complete system of values in which every want of every person or group has a definite place is necessary to provide an answer” (p. 86). The Soviets and the Nazis tried to impose that system of values.
     Hayek traced the ideas of national-socialism back to the time when they still had not been united by a hyphen. He reviewed the intellectual atmosphere that prevailed before Hitler gained supreme power over Germany. In The Road to Serfdom he showed how socialist thinkers had removed the obstacles for Hitler by sneering at the notion of the rule of law. He provided names and dates. In particular, he analyzed the ideas of Werner Sombart, a Marxist economist that became one of intellectual props of the Nazis. In the Germany of the 30s, the fight between communists and national-socialists was the inevitable and savage struggle for power between different collectivistic parties. However, both had a common enemy, says Hayek, in the bourgeois morality and its respect for limits and principles. Both Communists and Nazis derided laissez-faire as anachronistic
     Certainly Nazism wasn’t a return to the rule of law and free markets. For its millions of supporters, it was an improvement on socialism. It was still planning backed with the full force of the State, but better. Four year plans instead of the Stalinist five year plan. One of the improvements of the Nazis was the result of a lesson they learned from the experiments of the Soviets. Lenin himself had taken notice of the havoc created by the complete collectivization of all enterprises. That is why he provided some room for private ownership in his NEP (New Economic Policy). Lenin vaguely understood that you don’t have to own the shop in order to run it. It is enough (and better) if you just give orders to the owners (the miserable people they still called “owners”). One of the many advantages of that scheme is that when your orders lead to chaos and poverty, you can blame the owners.
     The Nazis extended Lenin’s NEP. They retained nominal owners for industries and shops, but all became executors of the State’s plans. Those capitalists who still clang to the notion that they directed their own enterprises found themselves in jail. For instance, Hugo Junkers, the inventor and entrepreneur that introduced new materials and techniques for the production of aircraft, was forced to give his patent rights to the government, his company was expropriated, and he was arrested. You are the owner, yes, but you must follow the orders, or you will quickly find that ownership has lost all substance. You are there to satisfy the bosses –and to take the blame for their mistakes.
     The Road to Serfdom includes a chapter entitled “Why the worst get on top” that shows how government enforced planning gives authority to people fond of exercising discretionary powers. Hayek shows why they must be discretionary and not subject to permanent rules. The chapter would sound very familiar to anyone who has worked under officials, judges, or bureaucrats who don’t recognize moral limits to their powers –only the power of those above them.
     One of the key distinctions we learn from Hayek is that between rules and orders (or in other words: between laws and commands). He says that rules are like traffic signs that show possible routes, forbid some turns, but don’t tell anyone where to go. In contrast, orders tell you where you have to go today, and tomorrow a new order may tell you to go to some order place. Orders are ad-hoc, they are dictated and replaced “on the merits”, that is: according to the evaluation that some leader or some board makes of individual circumstances.
     Hayek showed that orders were the basis of the command economy of the Soviets and Nazis, and to some extent of the interventionist policies of many Western governments. Still today, many people do not recognize any regulation other than that based on commands. For them, an economy based on general and permanent rules simply lacks order.
     The Road to Serfdom was first published in 1944. It was reprinted many times, and Hayek added new prefaces in 1956 and 1976.

A law professor says Hayek overvalued the rule of law
     In 1977, Joseph Raz, a professor at Oxford specialized in the philosophy of law, wrote and article in which he tried to show that the renewal of interest in the concept of the rule of law was largely unjustified and based on a fallacy. His article was later included in one of Joseph Raz’s books (The Authority of Law. Essays on Law and Morality, published in 1979 and reprinted in 2002. When I cite pages in Raz’s article, I refer to this book).
     Raz’s article was entitled The Rule of Law and its Virtue. The title was somewhat misleading and could have better sum up Raz’s main conclusion by saying: “The Rule of Law and its little Virtue”.
     Raz’s didn’t dispute Hayek’s conceptual and historical account of the notion of the rule of law. On the contrary, he started his article saying that “F.A. Hayek has provided one of the clearest and most powerful formulations of the rule of law” (p. 210). Raz’s line of attack was different: he asserted that there was not much value in the rule of law, and he finished his article saying that “Sacrificing too many social goals on the altar of the rule of law may make the law barren and empty” (p. 229). From the beginning of his article he said that Hayek’s conclusion was a fallacy. That fallacy was in Raz’s opinion “the assumption of its [the rule of law] overriding importance”. He announced that his purpose was to show that Hayek’s conclusions about the value of the rule of law were mistaken (p. 210).

Raz failed to understand Hayek’s book
     Certainly, Hayek never said that adherence to the rule of law overrides in importance any other value. Rather, he said that the attempts of planners (be they do-gooders, tyrants, or a combination of the two) that neglected the rule of law led to poverty and serfdom. Hayek never said that respect for the rule of law was more important than values like freedom and progress. Rather, he said that they come together, and in fact came together in history. The first chapter of The Road to Serfdom is entitled The abandoned roadRespect for the rule of law was a road. A road leading where? To the spectacular advances that Western nations achieved in the XIX century, and to those still in the future. So it is highly misleading to say that Hayek thought that the rule of law overrides any other value. It was the road to them. He never suggested that liberty and progress should be sacrificed on the altar of the rule of law. By abandoning it, one followed The Road to Serfdom. That was plainly clear in the book.

Hayek shows why planners cannot tie themselves to general and permanent rules
     Let’s see how Hayek described the conflict between the rule of law and planning (I will have to cite Hayek at some length in order to show later that Raz misunderstands him): “The planning authority cannot confine itself to providing opportunities for unknown people to make whatever use of them they like. It cannot tie itself down in advance to general and formal rules which prevent arbitrariness. It must provide for the actual needs of people as they arise and then choose deliberately between them. It must constantly decide questions which cannot be answered by formal principles only, and, in making these decisions, it must set up distinctions of merit between the needs of different people as they arise and then choose deliberately between them. It must constantly decide questions which cannot be answered by formal principles only, and, in making these decisions, it must set up distinctions of merit between the needs of different people. When the government has to decide how many pigs are to be raised or how many busses are to be run, which coal mines are to operate, or at what prices shoes are to be sold, these decisions cannot be deduced from formal principles or settled for long periods in advance. They depend inevitably on the circumstances of the moment, and, in making such decisions, it will always be necessary to balance one against the other the interests of various persons and groups. In the end somebody’s views will have to decide whose interests are more important and these views must become part of the law of the land, a new distinction of rank which the coercive apparatus of government imposes upon the people” (page 82, Fiftieth Anniversary Edition).

     The difference between enacting permanent formal rules and taking decisions “on the merits” of ever changing situations can be compared to that “between providing signposts and commanding people which road to take”. Formal rules such as those that describe the requisites of contracts or the consequences of failing to fulfill one’s promises “refer to typical situations into which anyone may agree and in which the existence of such rules will be useful to a great variety of individual purposes. The knowledge that in such situations the state will act in a definite way, or require people to behave in a certain manner, is provided as a means for people to use in making their own plans. Formal rules are thus merely instrumental in the sense that they are expected to be useful to yet unknown people, for purposes for which these people will decide to use them, and in circumstances which cannot be foreseen in detail. In fact, that we do not know their concrete effect, that we do not know what particular ends these rules will further, or which particular people they will assist, that they are merely given the form most likely on the whole to benefit all the people affected by them, is the most important criterion of formal rules in the sense in which we here use this term. They do not involve a choice between particular ends or particular people, because we just cannot know beforehand by whom and in what way they will be used.” (p. 83, I have added emphasis in bold letters for reasons that will be clear later).
     Hayek continues: “In our age, with its passion for conscious control of everything, it may appear paradoxical to claim as a virtue that under one system we shall know less about the particular effect of the measure the state takes…Yet this consideration is in fact the rationale of the great liberal principle of the Rule of Law”. That Raz failed to understand the paradox will be clear later.
     Hayek provides two arguments for the superiority of formal rules. One is economic: “the state should confine itself to establishing rules applying to general types of situations and should allow the individuals freedom In everything which depends on the circumstances of time and place, because only the individuals concerned in each instance can fully know these circumstances and adapt their actions to them. If the individuals are to be able to use their knowledge effectively in making plans, they must be able to predict actions of the state which may affect these plans. But if the actions of the state are to be predictable, they must be determined by rules fixed independently of the concrete circumstances which can be neither foreseen nor taken into account beforehand” (p. 84). That explains why government enforced planning is less productive than free enterprise.
     Hayek presents also a moral and political argument in favor of formal rules. “If the state can exactly foresee the incidence of its actions, it means that it can leave those affected no choice…General rules, genuine laws as distinguished from specific orders, must therefore be intended to operate in circumstances which cannot be foreseen in detail, and, therefore, their effect on particular ends or particular people cannot be known beforehand. It is in this sense alone that it is at all possible for the legislator to be impartial. To be impartial means to have no answer to certain questions –to the kind of questions which, if we have to decide them, we decide by tossing a coin” (pages 84-85)Who is to benefit more from a contract over futures? What industry can make better use of iron? Formal rules have no answers for these questions. And that is both efficient and impartial.
     But in planning the government “must, of necessity, take sides, impose its valuations upon people and, instead of assisting them in the advancement of their own ends, choose the ends for them…the state ceases to be a piece of utilitarian machinery intended to help individuals in the fullest development of their individual personality and becomes a ‘moral’ institution –where ‘moral’ is not used in contrast to immoral but describes an institution which imposes on its members its views on all moral questions whether these views be moral o highly immoral. In this sense the Nazi or any other collectivist state is ‘moral’, while the liberal state is not” (p. 85, emphasis added for reasons that will be clear later).
     Again on the moral argument for formal rules, Hayek says “equality before the law is in conflict, and in fact incompatible, with any activity of the government deliberately aiming at material or substantive equality of different people, and that any policy aiming directly at a substantive ideal of distributive justice must lead to the destruction of the Rule of Law. To produce the same result for different people, it is necessary to treat them differently. To give the same objective opportunities in not to give them the same subjective chance”. That is the different between equality under the law and equality of outcome.
     Hayek admits that “It cannot be denied that the Rule of Law produces economic inequality –all that can be claimed is that this inequality is not designed to affect particular people in a particular way. It is very significant and characteristic that socialists (and Nazis) have always protested against ‘merely’ formal justice, that they have always objected to a law which had no views on how well off particular people ought to be, and that they have always demanded ‘a socialization of the law’”. He says that the legal theorist of National Socialism, Carl Schmitt, was not altogether false when he opposed the liberal Rechstaat (i.e. the Rule of Law) and the ideal of the gerechte Staat (i.e. the just State). Where I live, Argentina, you can fill many libraries with books and articles that still today repeat Carl Schmidt’s words.

Raz's objetion: the same made by Socialists and Nazis
     We must assume that Raz read The Road to Serfdom. But then it is clear that he failed to understand what he read. Let’s see what Raz says against Hayek’s arguments. Raz writes that the rule of law “is not a moral virtue has such” (p. 226). It has only a negative value, it prevents arbitrariness, but adds no positive good. Raz admits that conformity to the rule of law is essential for securing whatever purposes the law is designed to achieve but it “also enables the law to serve bad purposes” (p. 225). It has only the virtue of an instrument; Raz compares it with a sharp knife, which can serve good or bad purposes. What counts are social goals, and they may justify departures from the rule of law. Raz concludes his article saying that we must not “make the law barren and empty” (p. 229).
     Raz repeats the objections of the socialists and Nazis, to which Hayek had already answered, with the difference that Raz uses the language of analytical philosophy instead of Socialist or Nazi rhetoric. He does not even mention Hayek's argument about the impossibility of agreement about plans, says nothing about the conflict with democracy, no reference to Hayek's historical analysis, no comment about Hayek's account of the erosion of the rule of law by socialist thinkers, no observation about Marx, Sombart, Schmidt, Laski,...nobody. Raz approaches the problem as if it had no history and no characters. He just repeats the objection to the rule of law made by socialists and Nazis and thinks that he has found a decisive argument.
     The socialists complained that bourgeois law had only formal value; Raz says that it has only a negative value. Carl Schmitt praised the advantages of the just State over the Rule of Law; Raz tell us not to sacrifice social goals on the altar of the rule of law. The Nazis fought to make the law a tool that would serve the material and moral needs of the Fatherland; Raz says that there is no moral value in the instrument as such, only in the goals it serves.

An instrument to whom?
     Raz misunderstands Hayek in yet another point. Hayek explains that formal rules that recognize general principles in advance can be used for people to make their plans –their own plans. In contrast, when Raz mentions goals and purposes he mostly refers to those of the lawmakers and judges.
     Raz does not deny that stable laws “provide a safe basis for individual planning” (p. 220). But then he seems to forget it and writes that “it is of particular importance to remember (?) that the rule of law is essentially a negative value. It is designed to minimize the harm to freedom and dignity which the law may cause in its pursuit of its goals however laudable these may be” (p. 228, emphasis added). Here we see that he assumes that the goals that the law serves are its goals. Hayek writes about the goals of the man who signs a contract to buy a shop with the idea of starting a company; Raz writes about the State’s goal.
     Again he writes that “The rule of law is essentially a negative value. The law inevitably creates a danger of arbitrary power –the rule of law is designed to minimize the danger created by the law itself…Thus the rule of law is a negative virtue in two senses: conformity to it does not cause good except through avoiding evil and the evil which is avoided is evil which could only have been caused by the law itself” (p. 224). According to that, the only purpose of the rule of law is to prevent the bad deeds of public officials in applying the law. But if there were no laws and officials, there would be no room for arbitrariness.
     Raz assumes that no good is ever done by the rule of law (no small company started with the security provided by a contract), only the prevention of harm from public officials. That a new company has started its life does not count as a good that law made possible, easier, or safer because it was an individual’s decision (not the law imposing its puposes on him) and that does not count.
     Raz confirms his notion about whose purposes laws serve when he writes: “We could divide the purposes a law is intended to serve into two kinds: those which are secured by conformity with the law in itself and those further consequences of conformity with the law or of knowledge of its existence which the law is intended to secure. Thus a law prohibiting racial discrimination in government employment has as its direct purpose the establishment of racial equality in the hiring, promotion, and conditions of service of government employees (since discriminatory action is a breach of law). Its indirect purposes may well be to improve race relations in the country in general, prevent a threat of a strike by some trade unions, or halt the decline in popularity of the government. Conformity to the rule of law does not always facilitate realization of the indirect purposes of the law, but it is essential to the realizations of its direct purposes…Therefore, if the direct purposes of the law are not to be frustrated it must be capable of guiding human behaviour, and the more it conforms to the principles of the rule of law the better it can do so” (p. 225). The law has direct and indirect purposes and it must guide people’s behavior so as to reach them. It is plain that Raz is not talking about people’s goals and plans.

No positive value?
     Raz’s focus on the purposes of the State prevents him from realizing that formal rules allow individuals to be truly moral. Whenever he sees no values imposed on people by the coercive apparatus of the State, he concludes that no value is served. Repeating the objections of the Socialists and Nazis, he fails to see that only true laws, those that have no other purpose than to serve the lawful purposes of individuals, allow individuals to be moral. 
     Should I work more in order to earn more? Or should I parade my misery and that of my children? Should I acquire those skills that people consider useful? Or should I ask the government to force others to pay me for what they don’t want? Should I be concerned about the education of my children? Or should I leave their education to community organizers and teenage gangs? All these are practical questions and also moral questions.
     The Nazis boasted that they had introduced morality into barren and empty laws. Point 19 in the Party’s program demanded “substitution of a German common law in place of the Roman law serving a materialistic world-order”. In fact, Weimar laws had already “advanced” a great deal in that direction. As Hayek acknowledges, in a way that boasting of the Socialists and Nazis was not without basis. A law that says that contracts should be interpreted so as to promote the interests of the nation, or of the working-class, has a moral purpose that a XIXth century code typically lacks. But it is that formal character of the rules that allows individuals to assume responsibility for their own lives. That is the paradox that collectivists of left and right failed to understand.
     Many years later, and in spite of the advantage of having Hayek’s books at his disposal, Joseph Raz repeated the mistake.

Wednesday, November 9, 2011

Who needs a replacement for Marxism?

This is the last article on the theories defended by Murphy and Nagel in the book The Myth of Ownership
At the end of The Myth of Ownership, Murphy and Nagel put their own ideas in historical context: “In the aftermath of the century during which the Marxist conception of equality played itself out, at enormous cost, the question is whether a different kind of egalitarian social ideal, one no intrinsically incompatible with capitalist economic institutions, can take hold in the Western democracies”.[1] Certainly Marxism has lost a considerable part of the luster it enjoyed for too long. But there is hardly a need for a replacement.
Actually, Marxism played itself out as a theory long before it was tried on people. Its many mistakes had been clearly demonstrated by the Austrian economist Eugene Böhm-Bawerk before the XIX century had come to an end (link to his article on the Marxist system). It was not necessary to try the poison on people. But it was tried. Then again, once it had produced the famines, the massacres, the show trials, the Gulag system of forced labor, it was not necessary to wait for decades till it finally crumbled in a pile of shame, to reach the conclusion that it was dead wrong. It was so from the start to those who suffered under it.
To many of those educated in the universities of the West, at long last, Marxism starts to look slightly less convincing; a bit less obviously true –though a poll conducted in Britain by BBC 4 in 2005, on its audience, gave Marx as the most important philosopher in history, well ahead of the rest. In other countries, large numbers of people adhere to Marx’s theories about exploitation and class struggle, but without caring about the origins of their ideas. In the US, however, the results of a poll similar to the one conducted by the BBC would have been different.
Marx thought that he had found a fundamental economic objection against capitalism. Against a system that was creating wealth and increasing population as never before in history, Marx did not use altruism and moral arguments (as, for instance, John Ruskin did). Marx thought that socialist production would be more efficient and avoid the contradictions he thought he had discovered in capitalism. Since Bohm-Bawerk’s article on the Marxian system, every informed economist knows that Marx had deluded himself –and misguided millions of people. Nevertheless, many economists and philosophers try to succeed where Marx failed: they try to show that capitalism is inefficient and must be corrected by the exercise of political power. They write theses that would prove that they have unearthed inefficiencies in the form of services wanted but not provided, public goods, free riders, natural monopolies, and a host of justifications for increasing intervention. It has become the surest path to a Nobel Prize in economics.
Murphy and Nagel think that their proposals could be accepted even in the US. They say that their theory is compatible with capitalism, or at least with some sort of capitalism. After all, they write “there is no natural or ideal market. There are many different kinds of market system, all equally free, and the choice among them will turn on a range of independent policy judgments”. Here, “independent” means: the decision should be taken independently of the value one may see in having a market system.
But what are the different free markets they have in mind? We must remember that highly praised thinkers would allow considerable latitude in the choice of the different kinds of market system: as said, John Rawls thought it natural to assume that free markets may or may not have private ownership of the means of production.[2] We do not know whether Murphy and Nagel would share Rawls’s view: their words about what must be left in private hands for the system to qualify as free market are vaguer than that of the master. But vagueness about “hindrances” and “conditions” is not a way to reconcile their theory with capitalism. At the very least, we must remember that Murphy and Nagel admit the morality of private property only in the form of a Hegelian minimum.
When we consider compatibilities and contradictions, we must understand that we are not assessing whether capitalism would survive a single day after theories like those of Murphy and Nagel are adopted, or would fall immediately. Of course, if all means of production are taken by the government, the market is killed –and Rawls’s assertion to the contrary will not keep it alive a single second. But there is also a slow death caused by “conditions” and “hindrances” incompatible with freedom. When we say, for instance, that heavy drinking is incompatible with a career in sports, we do not say that a successful sportsman will fail the day after he starts drinking too much. A very gifted individual may overcome some of the worst consequences for some time. But there is nevertheless a contradiction, something that drags him down, and it would be better for the drinker to recognize it as such. To be sure, a mangled market would work, some capital would be accumulated under the worst conditions, and inventiveness would fight bureaucracies for a long time. But, as with the sportsman, things would never be what they could have been.
It is worth noticing that Hegel himself did not suggest that property should be divided between a minimum that deserves full legal protection as a right, and another larger portion that lacks it. There is nothing in Hegel’s justification of property rights that restricts it to some portion of goods. Anyway, it would be of historical interest to discuss whether it is fair to attribute to him that distinction but, of course, it would not settle the question whether it makes sense.
For their part, Murphy and Nagel assume that the distinction is quite obvious, and tell us that the right to do whatever we want with a minimum of personal belongings does not cover “the freedom to engage with minimal hindrance or conditions in significant economic activity of the sort that drives a market economy”.[3] Now, what is capitalism if we take from it the freedom related to the significant activity that drives it? Steve Jobs would have been allowed to drive his car, but not Apple; Cornelius Vanderbilt would have been allowed to do what he wanted with a small boat, but not with his ship company.
Murphy and Nagel trace a line: any encroachment upon the Hegelian minimum would need exceptionally strong justification from the government, but not if it applies to property that is larger than that: “Some forms of personal discretion –including the basic Hegelian right to hold personal property– are at the core of the self, but unimpeded economic freedom is not one of them”.[4] They repeat it: “While the protection of some form of private property is an essential part of human freedom, the overall structure of the system of property rights should be determined largely on other grounds”.[5] That is to say, they are not part of human freedom.
Again we recognize that lack of perspective that we encountered in the discussion about incentives for work. It may be true that personal property like a comfortable house, a good salary paid by a prestigious university, a car, a personal library, and a few other things may be enough to allow a philosopher to pursue happiness. But Henry Bessemer –the inventor of mild steel– needed smelters; and Henry Ford needed production lines; and Robert Noyce –of INTEL– needed semiconductors. A Hegelian minimum would have not been enough for them, and the rest of us is no worse for that.
Certainly, what the debunkers of ownership have in store for capitalism is described in very general words: what is the kind of “hindrance” in the economic decisions of entrepreneurs that the government can impose without need of any strong justification (which would be needed if it affected an undefined Hegelian minimum)? We would not know until it has been imposed. In fact, we cannot expect anything more precise because the decisions that may be necessary to adopt cannot be known in advance, as proper legal rules are and must be. Friedrich Hayek explained long ago that a government that sets about deliberately distributing wealth, taking from some and giving to others, cannot tie itself to rules known in advance.[6] A government that directs its action mostly to the enforcement of general rules leaves to individuals the responsibility of deciding what is best for them according to present and future conditions, as they judge them.  But a government that tries to redistribute wealth must treat people differently, and in order to be effective it must take into account their changing needs. It must decide questions “on the merits”, that is, taking into consideration individual circumstances. It must watch the evolution of the economy, decide who is to get what now, and decide it again next year.
Nothing of that can be asserted in advance. Unless, of course, it is framed in vague words like “fair allocation”, and “reasonable payment” (and “hindrance”), with the usual provisions that “exceptional circumstances” (as judged when they present themselves) may justify distinctions. So, in a way it is not always true that collectivistic politicians and thinkers hide their plans from us in order to avoid resistance. Even if they wanted to be precise about what they will do to us (which is seldom the case) they could not do it.
Capitalism –even of the kind we have, which includes considerable government intervention– will be seriously affected if the theory that guides its course states, like Murphy and Nagel do, that “Evaluation must decide how 'mine' and 'yours' ought to be determined; it cannot start with a set of assumptions about what is mine and what is yours. The right answer will depend on what system best serves the legitimate aims of society with legitimate means an without imposing illegitimate costs”.[7] That evaluation, inevitably, will be left to the government –the legitimate means will be determined in the same way. What is crucial is that to justify or reject the decision –the authors declare– we “cannot appeal, at the fundamental level, to property rights.”[8]
However, we must realize that property rights that are secured against the changes in the “evaluation of what is mine and yours” are a fundamental requisite for capitalism. Murphy and Nagel’s theory is not really compatible with it. Indeed, if such redefinitions of mine and yours were possible, the rule that protects private property in the 5th Amendment of the US Constitution would mean nothing. Nevertheless, professor Waldron writes “The slogan that property is a human right can be deployed only disingenuously to legitimize the massive inequality that we find in modern capitalist countries”.[9]
Murphy and Nagel call the basic tenets of capitalism, “extreme libertarian”,[10] and sometimes, “everyday libertarianism”.[11] This is highly inaccurate. Libertarian-anarchism has never been implemented in the US, and it is not against the remote chance that it would ever be adopted that Murphy and Nagel argue. They reject the usual and general notion of ownership, they call for redistribution of wealth through cash transfers, and they claim that governmental “hindrances” on entrepreneurship do not need strong justification. Their objections apply really to capitalism.

 The tenets of collectivism
As Marxists and Socialists before them, Murphy and Nagel do not see any relevant difference between general rules under which individuals follow different roads (some successfully, some not), and a system that treats individuals differently in order to reduce a gap between their incomes or to achieve some other social goal.
At the end of the day, we are told, both systems are no more than different ways of allocating resources. One of them generates differences of wealth among individuals, the other generates more equality. The main difference lies in the effects. That these effects are the result of free competition or of government’s coercion is an irrelevant detail of no moral significance. After all, if it is true that taxes are imposed on individuals and that they cannot resist them, it is also true that success is imposed on them by luck, social factors, and even genetics. All of that is, in one way or another, external to people.[12]
Moreover, is it not true that coercion is used to prevent and punish robbery? Certainly, welfare payments put money in the pockets of some people after taking it from others –by force if necessary. But policing the streets and punishing criminals makes it possible for money to remain in the pockets of people, who would have been robbed otherwise. It is argued that these are just two ways of using the force of the state. We cannot say that one is substantially different from the other in any respect, apart from the different distribution of wealth that results from them.
Using this strategy, Cass Sunstein rejects the distinction between negative and positive rights. Just to remind the reader: classic rights like ownership and freedom of trade are often called “negative rights” because people exercise them by themselves; laws may protect them against violence and fraud but no law is necessary to exercise them. In contrast, positive rights consist in help that people are entitled to get from the government. Why are they called “positive”? Because their exercise requires, not merely the absence of harm, but a positive transfer of goods and services.
Now we return to Sunstein. There is no essential difference, says he: welfare payments cost money, but so does the justice system. In both cases the government has to spend money.[13] Someone receives help from the government in the form a cash transfer, and another by being defended against robbers and murderers. Of course, the comparison obscures the fact that those who receive cash transfers are also protected against criminals. But if one forgets it, one may be led to think that we just have two different ways of helping different people.
These arguments are seriously presented as a proof that our common understanding of the issues involved rests on mere prejudice. However, even a child recognizes that there is a big difference between begging his mother to carry him in her arms, and walking on his own legs. You may try to convince the child that there is no essential difference, and point out that when he struggled with uncertain steps trying to reach the other side of the room for the first time, mommy was there ready to stop an unruly brother from tripping his legs. You see, there is no real difference, there was help in both cases –there was a condition anyway. If you abandon your childish myths you would realize that being carried or walking yourself are just two different means of locomotion.
A child would not be convinced of that, but an adult might think that he cannot rationally reject the suggestion that ownership is a myth, as it is claimed in books hailed by experts as masterpieces; books brimming with references and lengthy examinations of what people would decide if they were not themselves. The reader of these books might have the vague feeling that there was something wrong somewhere in the arguments, that big and important things have disappeared from his eyes without him knowing how. I have tried to show by what means they disappear.
What Murphy and Nagel dismiss as mere myth, as entirely imaginary, as “morally irrelevant”[14] are some of the basic principles of capitalism. In the past, collectivism used to be forced upon us with the claim that it was historically inevitable. If you wanted to avoid being looked as a hick, you had to acknowledge that property rights and such were myths, part of a superstructure made for the defense of capitalism –which was a contradictory system. Only thick-headed people could delude themselves into thinking that they could answer these arguments.
Today you are told that your attachment to your property is merely a foggy notion that would not resist a thorough philosophical examination. Your resistance is proof of your lack of understanding. Your must avoid to be caught being –in Cass Sunstein words– “comically implausible”. However, again and again, we find that the theories that are hailed as fundamental contributions to our knowledge are really based on reasoning that is shockingly weak. And we find that the “myths” that are to be destroyed are the most fundamental principles that define the modern world. They are those that explain the difference between the age of the Pharaohs and our age.





[1] Pages 188-189.
[2] A Theory of Justice, pages 57 and 137. Harvard University Press. Revised Edition 1999. Also in Distributive Justice: Some Addenda, in Collected Papers, page 159. Harvard University Press. Paperback edition 2001.
[3] P. 64.
[4] P. 66.
[5] P. 45.
[6] The Road to Serfdom, Chapter 6.
[7] P. 75.
[8] Same page.
[9] The Right to Private Property, p. 5.
[10] P. 65.
[11] P. 36.
[12] At the base of many justifications of redistribution lies the odd idea –assumed but never discussed– that individuals must not be considered as individuals (defined as such by their qualities and defects and judged according to them), but as ghosts that later on will receive their own personal characteristics. These are not essential or defining of anything, but accidents that ghosts –the true object of political theory– suffer in their transit to this world. Ghosts must be protected from the morally irrelevant accident that makes them individuals.
[13] The Second Bill of Rights, p. 197. In Argentina, Roberto Gargarella, a law scholar who blends Marxism with constitutional law, repeats Sunstein’s arguments to reject the distinction between negative and positive rights: Carta Abierta sobre la Intolerancia, 51 Siglo XXI Editores 2006.
[14] P. 99.